The
previous essays in this series presented the Objectivist concept of free will,
and demonstrated how it operates in the mental and physical realms. In this
essay, the Objectivist view of volition will be compared with some past
theories of free will. Three broad views of volition will occupy the first half
of this paper: free will as the choice of actions, as the choice of motives,
and finally, as the choice of ideas. Afterwards, a response will be given to
each of these views, pointing out certain missing information or other flaws. The
essay’s conclusion will discuss how the Objectivist theory of free will is a
more holistic version of human choice than these past theories have offered.
Free Will as Choice of Actions
Philosophers
in both antiquity and in modern times argued that free will centered around one’s
choice of actions. Ancient Stoics, such as Chrysippus, and the more recent
Existentialists were major supporters of this view.
Chrysippus
(c. 280—207 B.C.E.) was the third head of the Stoic school, and a major
developer of its philosophy. His view of the universe is deterministic: Fate governs
all, and is set by Providence/God, and thus with “spirit,” with the divine.
Even still, he held that people are responsible agents because a part of one’s
actions is determined by oneself internally, instead of being preordained by the
distant past. More specifically, he believed that one can choose to assent to
or not assent to an action. Though, in the grand scheme of things, he felt that
God’s foreknowledge ultimately made humanity fated as well (“Chrysippus,” Information
Philosopher, passim).
(This
strongly represents a Compatibilist philosophy, which is the view that both free
will/volition and determinism are compatible. It is not hard to see from his
combination of free choice with fate that he’s most likely the first
Compatibilist in the history of philosophy.)
Though
the Existentialists (e.g. Sartre, Camus) differed in the details of their
philosophies, they certainly shared some similarities when it comes to the
position of free will. (Exceptions like Nietzsche aside, who denied free will.)
The Existentialists held a position quite opposite from the Stoic Chrysippus:
for them, there was no divine or absolute/intrinsic meaning in the world. One is free to act as one pleases, and one must find one’s own meaning through one’s
actions. People exist, but what each individual essentially is and what each person will do with their lives is directly up to them through their choice of actions. For Sartre, one’s
actions create one’s values, not the other way around: there is no ready-made
set of values to follow, and so each person makes their own natures by acting,
taking a stand, doing things and determining their values thereby (“existence
precedes and commands essence”) (“Existentialism: An Introduction,” passim).
Nigel
Warburton, Philosophy Now magazine
writer, notes the following about Sartre’s version of Existentialism:
The basic given of
the human predicament is that one are forced to choose what one will become, to
define oneself by one’s choice of action: all that is given is
that one are, not what one are. Whilst a penknife’s essence is
pre-defined (it isn’t really a penknife if it hasn’t got a blade and won’t
cut); human beings have no essence to begin with:
‘… man first of
all exists, encounters himself, surges up in the world – and defines himself
afterwards. If man as the existentialist sees him is not definable, it is
because to begin with he is nothing. He will not be anything until later, and
then he will be what he makes of himself’ (p.28).
So for the
penknife essence comes before existence; whereas for human beings the reverse
is true. . . (A Student’s Guide, para 7.)
For
philosophers like these, human actions are irreducible primaries, “first
causes” of consciousness.
Free Will as Choice of Motives
St.
Thomas Aquinas (1225–1274), wrote in the Summa Theologiæ of a complicated
relationship between the intellect, the appetite (faculty of motives and desires),
and their relation to the will.
In one passage concerning
free will, Aquinas described this relationship:
There are two types of
knowledge, sense and intellectual, and there are accordingly two sorts of
appetites. Sensory knowledge (understanding of particular facts) leads to sense
appetite, the desire of animals and people towards concrete, particular goods.
Intellectual knowledge brings about intellectual appetite, which are people’s
desires for more abstract, universal goods (which Aquinas thought would
culminate in an involuntary movement towards the ultimate good, God, in a
vision after death) (Magee, para 4–6). More broadly, the intellect “understands”
some things in the form of simply accepting them, such as first principles/axioms,
while individuals “reason” that some knowledge or conclusion has some sort of
logical connection to some other premise or principle already assented to. In a
similar manner, people’s appetites “will” a simple desire, such as a desire for
a specific end (believed to be desired for itself), and “choose” something
because it can be used to gain something else, which puts these objects in a
“means-end” relationship (Aquinas, Summa Theologiæ, Question 83, Article
4).
A philosopher, Eleonore
Stump (1947– ), once presented a simplified version of his theory concerning
the intellect and the will:
1.
Intellect
- apprehends a situation and determines that a particular end is appropriate
(good) for the given circumstances.
Will - approves a simple volition for that end (or can reject, change the subject, etc.)
Will - approves a simple volition for that end (or can reject, change the subject, etc.)
2.
Intellect
- determines that the end can be achieved, is within the power of the agent.
Will - Intention: to achieve the end through some means
Will - Intention: to achieve the end through some means
3.
Intellect
- Counsel: determines various means to achieve the end.
Will - accepts these means (or can ask for more means)
Will - accepts these means (or can ask for more means)
4.
Intellect
- determines the best means for the given circumstances.
Will - Electio (choice): selects the means the intellect proposes as best.
Will - Electio (choice): selects the means the intellect proposes as best.
5.
Intellect
- Command: says "Do the best means!"
Will - Use: exercises control over the body or mind as needed. (“Aquinas,” Information Philosopher, para 6)
Will - Use: exercises control over the body or mind as needed. (“Aquinas,” Information Philosopher, para 6)
Aquinas
himself says, “The proper act of free-will is choice: for we say that we have a free-will because we can take one thing while
refusing another; and this is to choose” (Question 83, Article 3). He also remarks,
Judgment, as it were,
concludes and terminates counsel. Now counsel is terminated, first, by
the judgment of reason; secondly, by the acceptation of
the appetite: whence [Aristotle] (Ethic. iii, 3) says that, ‘having
formed a judgment by counsel, we desire in accordance with that counsel.’
And in this sense choice itself is a judgment from
which free-will takes its name. (Ibid.)
Philosophers
like Aquinas viewed free will as fundamentally about choosing which motives or
desires will play a part in determining one’s chosen actions. (Even though in
Aquinas’ case, God is always the “First Cause” of everything (Aquinas, Summa Theologiæ, Question 83, Article 1, Reply to Objection 3).)
Free Will as Choice of Ideas
William
James (1842–1910) was another philosopher with a very intricate theory of free
will, and argues that volition ultimately controls any individual’s conceptual
abilities, actions, and even a person’s feelings.
From
my research, William James held that volition is fundamentally about the
maintenance and control of cognitive attention. “The essential achievement
of the will, in short, when it is most 'voluntary,' is to ATTEND to a
difficult object and hold it fast before the mind. . . . Effort of
attention is thus the essential phenomenon of will” (James, 1891, 561-562, emphasis in original).
Granting
one’s cognitive attention towards an idea without relinquishing it is the main
task of a volitional being:
“Everywhere
then the function of the [volitional] effort is the same: to keep affirming and
adopting a thought which, if left to itself, would slip away.” (Ibid., p. 565,
note 66. Bracketed word added.)
And:
To sum it all up
in a word, the terminus of the
psychological process in volition, the point to which the will is directly
applied, is always an idea. There are at all times some ideas from which one shy away like frightened horses the
moment one get a glimpse of their forbidding profile upon the threshold of one’s
thought. The only resistance which one’s
will can possibly experience is the resistance which such an idea offers to
being attended to at all. To attend to it is the volitional act, and the
only inward volitional act which we ever perform. (p. 567)
It
should be noted that William James includes “express consent” as a sometimes necessary,
secondary element:
The effort to
attend is therefore only a part of what the word 'will' covers; it covers also
the effort to consent to something to which one’s attention is not quite
complete. Often, when an object has gained one’s attention exclusively, and its
motor results are just on the point of setting in, it seems as if the sense of
their imminent irrevocability were enough of itself to start up the inhibitory
ideas and to make us pause. Then we need a new stroke of effort to break down
the sudden hesitation which seizes upon us, and to preserve. So that although
attention is the first and fundamental thing in volition, express consent to the reality of what is attended to is often an
additional and quite distinct phenomenon involved. (Ibid., p. 568)
For
James, what ideas people hold and what beliefs they use to guide their lives
are directly chosen by them.
Next,
one'll consider what Objectivism would have to say about these theories.
Responses to the Three Alternative
Theories
The Objectivist
view of volition has fresh perspectives that inform the three previous theories
mentioned. To draw these insights out, an investigation into what’s problematic
about these view is required.
Concerning
Choice of Actions as the Primary Form of Free Will
Objectivism
defends the view that human beings are free to choose their courses of actions
and behaviors, but disagrees with the position that individuals directly control their actions. One’s
actions are shaped and influenced by one’s knowledge, beliefs, values, desires,
and the decision to act on these mental resources (Binswanger 1991). Whether
one’s actions happen impulsively or after long drawn-out deliberations, it’s
still the case that a mental operation(s) of some sort occurred at some point
before the action, giving the action its purpose and greater context. It is
sometimes the case that a person does not know what motivates or explains his
or her actions due to insufficient introspection or the impulsiveness of the
act itself leaving little room for reflection, but it’s never the case that
human action is severed from operative mental actions.
Generally,
the Objectivist view is that “[m]an has the ability to reflect upon and
evaluate his own decision-making processes, and thus to control the processes
that control his actions” (Binswanger, p. 333, 2014). People observably don’t drive,
play with their siblings, or pick up a book to read aimlessly or randomly;
these actions, and others which can be more complex (or more simple), cannot be
carried out without some prior knowledge and some value-judgments being decided
beforehand.
More
importantly, it would be a nominal freedom to only control one’s actions, and
not one’s mental contents and mental actions. This view of volition as merely
choice of action denies one’s wondrous control of one’s mental life, the
ability to regulate the rationality of one’s thoughts and decisions, and the
ability to choose the ideas and values that will motivate one’s future courses
of actions. It’s a hampered form of free will: free in action supposedly, but
not free regarding one’s rational processes and the formation of one’s guiding
beliefs and values, and unable (supposedly) to change or improve them. To put
the point more bluntly: if the mind controls the body, then it’s nonsensical to
speak of freely choosing actions when one’s mind is itself not free.
Rather,
human actions are free because human minds are free, the mind volitionally
controls and regulates behaviors and courses of action. Nathaniel Branden (1930–2014;
pre-Break with Rand) notes the following about the Objectivist view of
volition:
In the Objectivist
theory of volition, a man is responsible for his actions, not because his actions
are directly subject to his free will, but because they proceed from his values
and premises, which in turn proceed from his thinking or non-thinking. His
actions are free because they are under the control of a faculty that is free—i.e., that functions volitionally.
(1964)
Concerning
Choice of Motives
This
level of choice is a more fundamental aspect of volition than that of choosing
actions, but freely choosing between motives or desires is still not a direct
or primary choice, according to Objectivism. Motives and desires do not come instantly
prepared for people to directly choose amongst them.
One’s
motives and desires are determined by one’s previously formed beliefs and
values, and one’s prior and current decision-making processes and deliberations
(Binswanger, p. 321, 2014). Motives for action and desires are automatic
responses to value-estimates one has made, which are in turn caused by the
conscious or subconscious premises and values that one has accepted (Branden,
1962; Branden, 1964). Like human physical actions, one’s motives and desires
aren’t chosen without background knowledge, beliefs, and value-judgments
conditioning them. Whether the given emotion is a longing for something, a
fear, a feeling of anger, or a feeling of wonder, these all depend on
subconscious evaluations that one has made of various things as being in some
way beneficial or detrimental to oneself (Binswanger, 1991).
The
granting of freedom to motives/desires without control over what one can believe
or value is also a hollow sort of freedom. It is by addressing and revising one’s
prior thinking and value-judgments (or non-thinking/failure to evaluate) that
one can change one’s motives, desires, and emotions. If this were not the case,
then one’s desires and emotions would have no connection to one’s knowledge and
values, and one would choose amongst one’s desires without reason or
explanation. This would mean that acts of decision-making and deliberation
would be pointless, since one’s thoughts and values would not influence them. St.
John of Damascus (c. 675 or 676–4 December 749), considered a father of the Eastern
Orthodox Church, once observed something insightful about deliberation:
But to prove that
the fairest and most precious of man's endowments [the power of deliberation] is
quite superfluous would be the height of absurdity. If then man deliberates, he
deliberates with a view to action. For all deliberation is with a view to and
on account of action. (An Exact
Exposition of the Orthodox Faith, Book II, Chapter XXV)
Each
person has control of their respective faculty of reasoning and ultimately
controls their evaluations of things, and thus each person has the power to
deliberate and choose how they will respond to their respective desires and
emotions.
Concerning Choice of Ideas/Value-judgments
On
the issue of fundamentals, this level is close to the true, deepest essence of
volition, but directly choosing ideas or values is not the crux of the issue. What
one comes to believe and to value depends upon the kind and scope of one’s
thoughts (Binswanger 1991, p. 8). The rationality (or irrationality) and the
logic (or illogic) of one’s thoughts will shape what ideas one will hold, and
what values one will adopt or create. This means that it is impossible to
logically demonstrate a given conclusion, and simultaneously not assent to it.
As Dr. Binswanger once put it: “To understand that X is the case is to believe X” (ibid.). It also means
that it’s impossible to prove that a good is beneficial to a person with
respect to his goals, interests, and tastes, and for the person rationally to
regard that good as a disvalue (or as a non-value).
Obviously,
people can disbelieve things in complete disregard of available evidence that
they’re privy to, or fail to appreciate something they know of that should be
valuable to them. But this is due to people evading
the thinking and conclusions that they’ve reached, making their knowledge
unreal to them. The evasion then acts as an intervening agent between their
prior thinking, and the conclusion and/or value-judgment they reach that
contradicts that thinking. The converse of what Binswanger said is also true:
it is psychologically impossible to concurrently
understand that X holds true and to still reject X (ibid., note 5).
Objectivist Volition as an Integrated View
of Choice
The
preceding suggested a general chain of choices that shift from more fundamental
to the most derivative. It suggested that the choice of ideas and values is
more fundamental than the choice of motives and desires, which is in turn more
fundamental than the choice of actions. There seems to be an assumption of
these prior theories that Objectivism addresses squarely and challenges directly: that one
can fully (or perhaps mostly) engage one’s conceptual abilities as one’s default mental state, that the use of
the conceptual level of consciousness is a given, just as perception is.
Objectivism
holds that the access to the cognitive abilities of the conceptual level is not given. The use and maintenance of one’s
conceptual level of consciousness is directly under one’s control, and that this
is accomplished by raising or lowering one’s degree of mental focus.
Focus
means many things. It means to take charge of one’s own mind, to set the mind
to the goal of full cognition. It means to have a mind resolutely directed
towards the awareness of reality, to “engage in cognitive self-regulation”
(ibid., p. 12). It also means being introspective, aware of and monitoring
one’s mental contents and physical actions. Obviously, a key point in
Objectivism is that focus, the essence of free will, is also the prime form of
rationality. (These descriptions are by no means exhaustive.) Drift, a form of
non-focus, is the failure to regulate one’s consciousness, to fail to
introspect when necessary, to not expend energy to be conceptually aware of
reality, to fail to be rational. Evasion, the other form of non-focus, is the
deliberate subversion of one’s conceptual awareness, to purposefully make an
item of reality seem unreal to oneself, to blank out certain facts because they
seem to be too scary or upsetting to face head-on.
The
Objectivist view is that the issue of focus or non-focus affects each of the
previous levels of choice mentioned in the alternative theories. One must focus
to reach rational thoughts and beliefs, and to form objectively beneficial
values. Focus is necessary to deliberate and evaluate things properly to automatize
the beliefs and values needed to form rational motives and desires. And focus
is required to ensure that one’s properly formed motives and desires are
translated into rational courses of actions. By the same token, non-focus will tend
to result in the belief in irrational ideas, in disvalues that factually harm
oneself, in detrimental motives and absurd desires, and in preposterous or
crazed actions. (The word “tend” was chosen because instances of drifting may
simply become the failure to think, the failure to evaluate, the failure to
form proper motives for action, and physical inaction, not some of the more obviously
self-destructive things that were just mentioned.)
All
three theories emphasize what one is
doing with one’s mind: deciding between different ideas and values, or between
different motives and desires, or between different courses of behavior and
action. But the proper emphasis should be on how one’s mind is being used: rationally or irrationally, focused
or evasively, mentally alert or passively. Human physical actions are preceded
by one’s motives and desires; these motives are preceded by deliberations and
evaluations automatized from one’s beliefs and values; and these very beliefs
and values are the result of the kind and of the extent of one’s thinking, the
rationality and the span of such thoughts. The Objectivist view stands as a
correction of and an advance over these past theories, while offering a more
holistic, integrated view of volition than these theories ever offered.
Conclusion: Focus as Precursor to Ideas/Values
and as Ultimate Motive
From
the above, it should be clear that Objectivism holds that the engagement of the
rational faculty, the choice of focus or non-focus, is the causal primary, the direct act of free will that was
discussed throughout this essay. As Peikoff clarifies, “‘Primary’ here means: presupposed
by all other choices and itself irreducible” (1991, p. 62).
This
means that choices at this level are first
causes within one’s consciousnesses, and cannot be causally explained by
any other factor besides one making the choice to focus (or not) oneself. Ideas
cannot induce one to focus because one needs to already be in focus to grasp new ideas, or to apply old ideas to a
present concern (ibid., para 5). Values also cannot be appreciated and used as
guides for action without an already active conceptual level awareness of them,
i.e., without focus (ibid.).
Lastly,
there can’t be some other desire or motive to explain why one would choose to
focus other than to be cognitively aware of reality (Binswanger, 1991, p. 18).
Any other human action, physical or mental, can be split up into the action and
the motive for that action. A woman could walk (action) to get some exercise in
for the day (motive). A student thinks (action) to solve a difficult geology
problem (motive). The action of focusing is cognitively regulating one’s
consciousness. The motive: to cognitively regulate one’s consciousness. Focusing
is the action of rising to the conceptual level of consciousness, or sustaining
that level of awareness. The motive: to rise to (or sustain awareness at) the
conceptual level. Being aware of reality is another way of describing the
action of focus. The motive: to be aware of reality. Focus then is the unconditional acceptance of reality, an
action which subordinates all other
motives and desires to whatever facts one must confront (ibid., pp. 17–19).
This is the way in which focus stands as the ultimate motive for a human
consciousness: the desire to use one’s rational faculty to deal with the facts
of reality.
References
Aquinas,
T. (2016). Summa Theologiæ. [Question
83, Articles 3–4]. Retrieved August 18, 2017
from
web site: http://www.newadvent.org/summa/1083
(Originally
published c. 1265–1274,
and revised in 1920)
Binswanger,
H. (2014). How we know: Epistemology on an Objectivist foundation.
New York,
NY:
TOF Publications.
Binswanger,
H. (2007). Volition as cognitive self-regulation. Irvine, CA: Ayn Rand
Bookstore.
(Original work published 1991 in Organizational
Behavior and Human
Decision Processes, 50(2), 154–178) doi:
10.1016/0749-5978(91)90019-P
Branden,
N. (1964). The Objectivist concept of free will versus the traditional concepts.
The
Objectivist
Newsletter, 3(1), 7–12. Irvine, CA: Second Renaissance Books.
Branden,
N. (1962). Intellectual ammunition department: Reason and Emotion. The
Objectivist Newsletter,
1(1), 3. Irvine, CA: Second Renaissance Books.
Chrysippus.
(n.d.). Retrieved August 25, 2017,
from Information Philosopher Web site:
http://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/philosophers/chrysippus
Damascene,
J. (n.d.). An exact exposition of the
Orthodox faith. Retrieved August 19, 2017 from
web
site: http://www.orthodox.net/fathers/exactidx.html
Existentialism:
An introduction. (n.d.). Retrieved August 25, 2017, from web site:
http://wdb.sad17.k12.me.us/teachers/bburns/com/documents/religion/exist.html
James,
W. (1891). Principles of psychology
(Vol. 2). [PDF version]. London: Macmillan.
Magee,
J. (n.d.). Aquinas and the freedom of the will. Retrieved August 21, 2017 from Thomistic
Philosophy
Page web site: http://www.aquinasonline.com/Topics/freewill.html
Peikoff,
Leonard. (1993). Objectivism: the philosophy of Ayn Rand. [PDF
version]. New York,
NY:
Meridian. (Original work published 1991)
Warburton,
N. (1996, Spring/Summer). A student’s guide to Jean-Paul Sartre’s
Existentialism
and
Humanism. Philosophy Now, 15.
Retrieved August 25, 2017, from web site:
https://philosophynow.org/issues/15/
A_students_guide_to_Jean-Paul_Sartres_Existentialism_and_Humanism
No comments:
Post a Comment