Previous: Objections to the Axioms (Part 2)
Question: “Are Axioms Proven or Merely Assumptions?”
Question: “Are Axioms Proven or Merely Assumptions?”
“Are first
principles or the axioms of logic (such as identity, non-contradiction)
provable? If not, then isn't just an intuitive assumption that they are true?[...]”[1]
The axioms are neither “proven” nor “assumed.”
(In the
Objectivist view of axiomatic corollaries, Aristotle’s “Laws of Thought” are
corollaries of the Existence axiom. And
more specifically, the Law or Principle of Non-contradiction and the Law of the
Excluded Middle are restatements/corollaries of the Law of Identity, which is a
corollary of “existence exists.”[2] So I’ll consider this question as broad
enough to encompass any first principle, including the Objectivist axioms.)
I’ll make several points about why this can’t be the case
when speaking of actual axioms.
Infinite Regress of Proofs
The first point is that there’s a logical implication to the
question: if the axioms are provable, doesn’t that mean that there’s something
antecedent to the axioms that prove them?
And if so, how are these antecedent axioms proved? There must be something else that proves
them. And so on for infinity.
It is impossible to prove everything. The attempt to prove everything including philosophical
axioms would go on forever and so the proof would never be finished (if the
requirement really is to prove everything). This was Aristotle’s original response to the
objection that everything needs a proof. (The objection was directed towards his
Law of Non-contradiction, but could be applied to any axiom. See his Metaphysics,
Book IV.)
Some observations and principles must be at the foundation,
the starting points which cannot be proved but are relied upon by all proofs.
No Proof from a Void
There is another reason why real axioms cannot be
proved.
This question being raised shows a kind of uncertainty about what constitutes a “proof.”
As Objectivism defines it in its broadest sense, it “is the process of
deriving a conclusion step by step from the evidence of the senses, each step
being taken in accordance with the laws of logic.”[3] This applies to both
inductive and deductive proofs: both are a series of principles/premises which
reach a certain conceptual product (an inductive generalization or deductive
conclusion) using the laws of logic and our sense-perception as the base and
ultimate proving ground.
The following description of “proof” is a bit more relevant
to my response, however: “Proof is the process of deriving a conclusion
logically from antecedent knowledge.”[4] Taking more basic knowledge you
already possess, you logically infer a series of principles or premises and end
with a more technical conclusion. But
axioms and their axiomatic concepts are
the most basic conceptual knowledge; there is no knowledge antecedent to the
axioms.
Rand once described the axiomatic concepts as “irreducible
primaries”: they are the very foundation for cognition and philosophy, and literally
cannot be “analyzed” or broken down into component parts. Such an analysis or proof would be
futile. Rand notes that, “([a]n attempt
to ‘prove’ them [axiomatic concepts] is self-contradictory: it is an attempt to
‘prove’ existence by means of non-existence, and consciousness by means of
unconsciousness.)”[5]
There is no antecedent knowledge or more basic alternative
facts with which to derive “existence,” “consciousness,” or “identity.” Without them, there is only a void. Nothing can be proved from nothing.
(A follow-up point is that you cannot assume what you are
trying to prove. Even a purported proof
of an axiom must rely on the axiom. In a
future post, I will reply to an objection about the “circular” nature of
axioms, in that the axioms rely on other axioms for their validity, and I will
discuss this point in more detail there.)
Starting Points as Not
Merely Assumptions
This all being said, the axioms are not assumptions, if this
implies that they are baseless, arbitrary starting points.
Without these starting points, there is nothing to consider
or discuss, and no one conscious to even consider or discuss these (non)
things. There is a “rhyme and reason” to
the discovery of axioms, and it is sense perception or direct introspective experience. Do you want to know if something exists? Open your eyes and/or ears (and/or your other
senses) and experience existence for yourself.
Do you want to know if you are conscious? Reflect on your decisions and dreams and
memories and realize that only a consciousness could be aware right now to
presently do all of these things.
Another point to consider is the common conception of
“assumption.” Dictionary.com defines
“assumption” as “a statement or formula that is stipulated to be true for the purpose
of a chain of reasoning: the foundation of a formal deductive system.”
This definition relies heavily on the philosophical
rationalist’s position on axioms: the axioms are used as the jumping off points
to begin spinning off deductive arguments and theories. But as I said in my previous post, the
Objectivist axioms do not serve as a founding platform for a deductively
constructed philosophy.
It is true that the theoretical (i.e., provable) principles of Objectivism
take the axioms for
granted. (In fact, I would argue that all theoretical principles of all disciplines must take these axioms for granted.) As far as discussing or proving
the non-axiomatic principles of Objectivism, the axioms are assumed as the
basic framework of the proof/discussion.
But the validation of the axioms is not taken for granted or an
arbitrary choice: it is metaphysically given as the phenomena of
sense-perception and introspection.
Conclusion
My point is that we’re not faced with two choices: (1) either
find a way to prove the axioms, or (2) admit that they are baseless claims that
we conveniently take for granted. Proof
is not the only way to establish an idea’s relationship to reality, according
to Objectivism. And the way to validate
or show a proper axiom’s connection to reality is direct experience. If anyone seeks to object to the
self-evident, then it is possible to show that even the objector must rely on
the axioms in his attempt to refute them: his capacity to gain and discuss
knowledge depends on the axioms. So the
case is that the axioms cannot and should not be proved, but we do not randomly
adopt the axioms, or take them for granted without grounds.
References and Notes
[1]: Part of a question at the Ask Philosophers site: http://www.askphilosophers.org/question/4821
[2]: In lecture 3 of Nathaniel Branden’s Basic Principles of Objectivism course,
he said: “The three Aristotelian laws of logic are: the Law of Identity, the
Law of Contradiction, [and] the Law of Excluded Middle. The last two are merely
corollaries or restatements of the first.” (Vision
of Ayn Rand: Basic Principles of Objectivism, Lecture 3: Logic and
Mysticism, p. 66.) As Rand considered
Branden’s collaborations before their split in 1968 as consonant with her
philosophy, his lecture course is still Objectivist material.
[3]: Leonard Peikoff, Introduction to Logic lecture series, Lecture 1.
[4]: Leonard Peikoff, The Philosophy of Objectivism
lecture series, question period, Lecture 3.
[5]: Ayn Rand, Introduction
to Objectivist Epistemology, Chapter 6: Axiomatic Concepts, p. 55.
No comments:
Post a Comment